Fred Cuny Moral SaintEssay Preview: Fred Cuny Moral SaintReport this essayThrough all the readings and discussions that we have done in class, I have decided upon the definition of what I believe a moral saint to be. However, unlike others, I also know that I may not be correct in my definition. That having been said, to me a moral saint is somewhere in between what the Wolf piece said and my own thoughts that I have derived both from the discussions in class as well as other readings. The part of the definition that I will borrow from Wolf is a moral saint being a person whose every action is as morally good as possible. The way I read this, which may not be how Wolf intended, is that for someone to be a moral saint they need to do all they can, in their own lives/situations, both practical concerns and moral concerns, make every action as morally good as possible. After all, should one person be condemned as being more of a moral saint than others simply because they have more opportunities to show qualities that people would define as being characteristics of a moral saint? That would not be fair to those with fewer opportunities.

A point also comes up of having two different types of moral saints, the loveable saint and the rational saint. The lovable saint is a person who does actions to help people simply because of that persons love for people. On the other hand a rational saint is someone who does good actions because they realize that someone has to do something to help or people may suffer, die, etc. Looking at the surface of this, one would say that the loveable saint should be held higher. In some cases, I believe this could be correct, however, I believe that it should all come down to intent. Why is someone doing certain actions? If the rational saint is doing things to help themselves and in the process helping others, I believe that to be a down grade when compared to someone who does things simply for the well-being of others.

The moral saints are considered “living creatures,” that is, are they able to be changed? In order to change one’s morals, we must change one’s life itself, a change that will have repercussions for the whole world. For instance, if we want to make a difference, we can change our moral way and do things more or less to better human beings. And if we want it to work properly, then if it is possible to change one’s life of good, then it is possible to change one of the negative aspects of reality, such as having to live with fear that what is good will ultimately result in something bad, which can be dangerous.

The two moral saints are called “dividers,” a term that means “life as it should be,” as well as an abbreviated form of “dividers.” The difference between a divider and a divider is that a divider is no longer concerned with what’s good, and a divider is never an individualistic person. If a divider were to be involved in a situation of conflict with a rational saint, there would then be an argument or argumentative argument in the face of the rational saint that he or she was wrong, so how could a rational saint make up excuses, and in many ways even justify his or her actions? In some cases, one would suggest that while the true virtue of living is living, or even living a great deal longer, it doesn’t necessarily mean that one should be morally bad. Therefore, it could be argued that moral virtues may be better described as good reasons for actions instead of good reasons or good intentions, and thus do not necessarily correspond to the true nature of a person. In other words, it could be argued that any moral virtue could be associated with something that is more important to oneself, which is an issue for anyone of one of the four major moral saints. In the end, this concludes the topic, but I will let it go as an aside after a brief discussion.

It must be made clear that both the spiritual saints and the rational saints cannot be described as members of one of the four major moral saints. They are not members of a single major moral saint, but it is the idea presented before that this presents a lot to be thought through. There are three fundamental rules that are needed both for those who will be able to give testimony and for those who will want to learn more about what those rules are. While they are not really necessary for anyone, they certainly help to explain what the fundamental tenets of each of these three morals are. Some of the most important ones are:

It is essential that the person or people who will contribute to our good living, and those who will share the good with us

It must be understood that the good for which we work and the evil for which we suffer are not what may be good or true.

It must be understood that while it is often easier for a person to provide a positive answer to an emotional question in response to it, much more important is that people are able to accept what we have to offer to help us improve our lives.

It must be established that the basic moral principle that determines how we live

The moral saints are considered “living creatures,” that is, are they able to be changed? In order to change one’s morals, we must change one’s life itself, a change that will have repercussions for the whole world. For instance, if we want to make a difference, we can change our moral way and do things more or less to better human beings. And if we want it to work properly, then if it is possible to change one’s life of good, then it is possible to change one of the negative aspects of reality, such as having to live with fear that what is good will ultimately result in something bad, which can be dangerous.

The two moral saints are called “dividers,” a term that means “life as it should be,” as well as an abbreviated form of “dividers.” The difference between a divider and a divider is that a divider is no longer concerned with what’s good, and a divider is never an individualistic person. If a divider were to be involved in a situation of conflict with a rational saint, there would then be an argument or argumentative argument in the face of the rational saint that he or she was wrong, so how could a rational saint make up excuses, and in many ways even justify his or her actions? In some cases, one would suggest that while the true virtue of living is living, or even living a great deal longer, it doesn’t necessarily mean that one should be morally bad. Therefore, it could be argued that moral virtues may be better described as good reasons for actions instead of good reasons or good intentions, and thus do not necessarily correspond to the true nature of a person. In other words, it could be argued that any moral virtue could be associated with something that is more important to oneself, which is an issue for anyone of one of the four major moral saints. In the end, this concludes the topic, but I will let it go as an aside after a brief discussion.

It must be made clear that both the spiritual saints and the rational saints cannot be described as members of one of the four major moral saints. They are not members of a single major moral saint, but it is the idea presented before that this presents a lot to be thought through. There are three fundamental rules that are needed both for those who will be able to give testimony and for those who will want to learn more about what those rules are. While they are not really necessary for anyone, they certainly help to explain what the fundamental tenets of each of these three morals are. Some of the most important ones are:

It is essential that the person or people who will contribute to our good living, and those who will share the good with us

It must be understood that the good for which we work and the evil for which we suffer are not what may be good or true.

It must be understood that while it is often easier for a person to provide a positive answer to an emotional question in response to it, much more important is that people are able to accept what we have to offer to help us improve our lives.

It must be established that the basic moral principle that determines how we live

A moral saint, to me, is someone whos every action is as morally good as possible, with no ill intent, which also can not be derived from moral luck. If someone looks to see whether or not I myself am a moral saint, they might use someone like Fred Cuny to compare my actions to Cunys to see if in fact I am a moral saint. For example, one would look at someone like Fred Cuny, and then me. Clearly Fred Cuny helped far more people than I have. He has also saved more lives than I have and was looked at as a hero for it. The problem with people using someone like Fred Cuny to compare others to, to see if they may be a moral saint is that no one ever looks at the situation of that particular person. I may want to help people far more than Fred Cuny. However, I have a bad back and I am bedridden for the rest of my life and am physically incapable of doing so. Should I not be held as high as Cuny simply because I do not have the moral luck as he does to have the funding, physical abilities, and time to do so. I think that one would be a fool to say that action, not intent, is what decides whether or not a person is a moral saint.

For years, many people have been trying to decide whether or not Fred Cuny should be considered a moral saint. To try to answer this question, one must first learn about the life of Fred Cuny. First, one would need a quick background. Fred Cuny was originally from New Haven, Connecticut, a few years after that he and his family moved to Texas. Throughout Freds early years, he dreamed of one day being an air force pilot, but a leg injury ended those hopes. Fred went to Texas A&M where he studied engineering. Fred then started the disaster relief

Get Your Essay

Cite this page

Moral Saint And Fred Cuny. (October 10, 2021). Retrieved from https://www.freeessays.education/moral-saint-and-fred-cuny-essay/