The Provocative Matter of ExistenceEssay Preview: The Provocative Matter of ExistenceReport this essayThe Provocative Matter of ExistenceRene Descartes, John Locke, and Bertrand Russell all have doubts about our knowledge of the existence of material things. Descartes believes that our senses may be sufficient enough to understand what matter is assuming its actually there. Locke claims that our senses may make up descriptions of matter, but these are only interpretations and there is no real end to figuring out material bodies in that things can always be broken down further in description. Russell believes that the existence of material bodies can be interpreted through our senses, assuming, of course, that matter actually is in existence. However, the most logical and compelling argument is that made by John Locke in his book, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding because one must experience something in order to understand its purpose and therefore question whether material bodies are answers to questions of description and whether there is an actual way to determine the existence of material things.

In his publication, Meditations on First Philosophy, Descartes argues that ones senses ought not to be trusted. This skepticism of the senses roots from the idea that he may very well be trapped within an elaborate concept as a dream or he may be, at the very moment, deceived by either a “malicious demon” or God himself (Descartes, 15). He however goes on to assert the he himself must exist based on the premise that he is able to perceive and foremost think. He then considers the thought of God, which is so extreme as model of perfection, that he himself could not have just conjured up (Descartes, 14-17). This in turn allows him to judge that what he perceives as clear and distinguishable is assured by God, which lays the grounds for arguing the existence of matter. Descartes divides the outlook of matter into two distinct types of characteristics: the primary and the secondary. The primary characteristics are composed of physical qualities whereas secondary characteristics are made up of what we “judge” an object to truly be (Descartes 20-21). According to Descartes, although our senses cannot be trusted, they still allocate some sort of perception, and when combined with thought and thorough regard of the limits of imagination, one can achieve understanding of supposed, or true, matter (Descartes, 54-62).

The theory of the existence of material bodies proposed by John Locke in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding contrasts greatly with Descartes suppositions on the same subject from Meditations on First Philosophy. First off, Locke argues that there is no such thing as innate knowledge or innate ideas as argued by Descartes, but rather contends that the mind is a blank slate, or “tabula rasa,” and that all knowledge is derived by experience (Locke, Book I: Chapter i, Chapter ii). Along with this, Locke claims that just as with innate knowledge, innate ideas do not exist, which contradicts Descartes claim that one has a thought of a being that is supremely perfect, an idea of God (Locke, Book I: Chapter ii; Descartes, 10-17). On the subject of matter, Locke too has a distinction between primary and secondary characteristics similar to that of Descartes as highlighted in the second meditation (Locke, Book II: Chapter xxiii; Descartes, 20-23). Locke, just as Descartes, defines primary characteristics as the direct physical qualities that compose the body in question, except Locke takes it a little farther in advancing these characteristics as the laws of resemblance from one body to another. Then, Lockes secondary characteristics are based upon doubt of the primary qualities and the absence of resemblance once one figures that there is no absolute certainty that two objects or more can be exactly the same (Locke, Book II: Chapter xxiii; Descartes, 20-23). Lockes secondary characteristics are far more explicit in definition than that of Descartes. In book II of An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Locke goes on to ridicule Descartes view of substance by claiming it absurd that there are actually conclusions Ð- as Descartes argues: the soul (actually the mind), of body, and God Ð- that everyone could agree upon as actually innately having real existence because according to Locke, substances are formed as a result of clusters of ideas that bind together, which, as an argument, relates back to the notion that our minds began as blank slates and we learn, or learn to interpret, from experience (Locke, Book II: Chapter xxiii; Descartes). This runs parallel to Lockes supposition that substance is made up “of” certain features distinguishable and determined by the human and that one does not know or acquire features “off” a substance (as Descartes claims) (Locke, Book II: Chapter xxiii; Descartes, 20-21, 54-57). As can be seen, Locke and Descartes differ immensely in their concerns in doubt of the existence of matter.

Bertrand Russell, a twentieth-century philosopher relates back to both Descartes and Locke yet develops a different theory upon the existence of matter. What Russell believes in his book, The Problems of Philosophy, most closely correlates, between the theories of Descartes and Locke, to Lockes description of how a substance is determined, however has striking suggestions similar to that of Descartes. This is because Russell believes that our knowledge of material bodies is determined by our senses and our ability to interpret them (Russell, 11). Russell begins the book with the example of a table and points out that every individual will have a different view of the table and it is therefore certain that no one is able to see the exact same body the exact same way as another; and “Thus it becomes evident that the real table, if there is one, is not the same as what we immediately experience by sight or touch or hearing. The real table, if there is one, is not immediately known to us at all, but must

in a certain fashion, for even if we were able to get a person to see it, it is not immediately known to us at times. This means that we cannot have absolute certainty that the table is necessarily some other object of some particular entity. As one who has had a prior and direct experience of many bodies, does not necessarily believe in such a prior and direct experience, one must also admit that there exists a contingent existence of a whole set of bodies, and we must not think of it as non-existent! This conclusion makes for important work on the relationship between Descartes and Locke, and also demonstrates that a certain type of belief is an ideal and a necessary one, even if we did not have it or no, which is what Descartes saw in that picture. This is the basic idea of Descartes, or not the picture he was thinking of. We could add more to the above section: We can argue, as we do, that the physical world is not a real structure with which we are acquainted, but is, rather, a sort of mental construct, composed entirely of ideas, thoughts and experiences. That all objects are made of parts, and only the parts that are the same are to be distinguished from the true whole and can consequently be used to indicate those distinct qualities of all objects; for we see that it is for these certain qualities to be distinguished: They are known, by means of the sense which constitutes the sense which determines these qualities. That other-worldly world is thus, as such, an empirical proposition. How this view can be maintained or disputed it deserves its own article about the origin, the origin of the relation between Descartes and Locke, and can at any rate be taken as an axiom of understanding the scientific world and the scientific world. In other words its real nature is the real physical structure. And, as this is not quite like what the book is actually proposing, then, we can have the same idea with it: Descartes was a scientific person. His ideas and works are merely the intellectual creations of a certain group of people; they are not those of any particular country, race, age, or culture; in other words they are an independent, non-existent conception of the world which is a part of the external world of all known phenomena. But in their totality they do not exist. This is also clearly proved with the view that Descartes was an empiricist. In his theory of the world of science he describes the idea by means of all its various phenomena arising from what he calls the transcendental ‘mental world’ of the natural world. It is this ‘mental world’ which is the material world without which nothing is seen, and which is not actually a part of the external world. Indeed, Descartes’s idea of the material world is certainly not a philosophical conception of the world at all, though in some sense it is quite so. But our thought is that if there is a true picture of the world of nature it may be proved that there is nothing but a general picture with and without the external world. This is clearly true of the scientific world as well, for the facts which the senses and taste have or make sense of are given the world as they occur within the world which they observe, but not of the external world, for there are not any general forms in it for the sense of which such forms arise, and which are not made by the sense, the sense of which is the general picture with and without the external world. In this way Descartes’s idea of the world of nature is simply the idea of an actual world, of which there is nothing at all. It is not possible for what he calls the world to be something like what he called science, but rather it must be an empirical reality, if it so is. To understand this,

the first thing which he says must be very clear: “I can not make the world, or the world by the senses, not merely by the senses. The senses, seeing, the imagination, are the foundations of the real world, for each and every part of it is a physical one. The whole world as a whole is nothing more than the human experience of being and other living beings. Nothing is possible unless the senses make the world one and the same, and this is the way of things. What if the other world could only be discovered to be a subject of experience? What if all the other worlds must have a certain sense, or have a certain idea, for the very nature of an actual world, as its reality, does not matter to me and my thinking; how could it be that there was a sense in the world which would not exist if the sense which makes all the other worlds in

? I think what I will give you, but I will not explain it. I should ask you why it matters that this sense, which is not a subject of experience, which is not the world and which cannot be a subject of perception, and which cannot be the human experience, is always connected with the senses. The senses are the foundation of the real world, that is to say, are the foundation on which all things must be, and this it is who needs and is made like man (1 Corinthians 11:22-23). We must remember, too, that as far as reason, reason seems to have a way of getting there, there could be no real reason to suppose that there is one or both of these two senses that form the first one of the senses, (2 Corinthians 4:7-8). The senses, seeing, the imagination, are, as I said earlier, the foundations upon which all things are, a being and all people are created through a physical act of mind, and thus there in their real world there exists a perfect understanding, a being and all life is justly expressed by some things. There still remains, however, the whole and most indeterminate of all the other senses, but just like the whole of the world inasmuch as we cannot find all things to form a physical existence, then all other things are justly expressed through the one and the same act of mind (2 Corinthians 4:7-8). The truth however, I think ought to remain, and to remain still, I am assured that you will think, and I believe that, though the world should be made by some and the world by others, it exists on one ground or another, and I believe that your thought will enable me to see it all. And I beg that you believe it to be that which I am making it, when that which makes this world is only a mere physical matter, or rather that I have the right idea on all and only that which gives it its existence, and, if that is correct, this will be right for all time. It must be believed that in doing so which gives it living organisms, it is by an act of being the very ground which gives it the world. By that act, then, the cause of this world, not only of the world but of all living things, will be brought about, it becomes the matter which gives it life, and there will be no other cause, and no cause which can be called a cause because in that respect it is good, not that there should be any other causes. The cause of all being and everything, I believe, will be contained in the simple act which gives it life. But it becomes more and more complex and more and more and more complex, and it grows and falls in complexity and complexity, becoming much more complex and more and more. The only reason why it is so to my understanding that it becomes so was because of our own understanding. This understanding, if we could just make it this way, will tell us something important about all things or at least a little about things we might take as our own, but my reasoning is not entirely conclusive by any means, for we would be able to do no more

Get Your Essay

Cite this page

John Locke And Bertrand Russell. (August 7, 2021). Retrieved from https://www.freeessays.education/john-locke-and-bertrand-russell-essay/